Page 302 - Gabrijela Kišiček and Igor Ž. Žagar (eds.), What do we know about the world? Rhetorical and argumentative perspectives, Digital Library, Educational Research Institute, Ljubljana 2013
P. 302
What Do We Know about the World?
2. Historic Roots of Imitatio in Rhetorical Pedagogy
2.1. The Ancient Theoretical Pedigree
Sophistic rhetoric identifies imitation as a necessary factor of the de-
velopment of successful orators. Besides, sophists are considered the first
imitators of oral rhapsodies (Schiappa, 1999: 6).
As regards Plato and Aristotle, they both accept the contribution of
imitation to learning even if they don’t perceive it as an emulating prac-
tice (Corbett, 1971: 243). For Plato, the positive or negative evaluation
of imitation depends on its role in the acquisition of the ideal truth. Fi-
nally, he approves its use as a medium capable of educating the Republic’s
future, ideal citizens (Plato, 1937; Tate, 1932: 161).
In Phaedrus Socrates presents an analogous bilateral attitude to-
wards it. On the one hand, he applies the art of imitation by offer-
ing a more accurate version of Lysias’ speech and he accepts, explicit-
ly, the existence of ideal models of orators. On the other hand, he ad-
vises Phaedrus not to imitate entirely a speech which contains bad ex-
amples of what he considers as true rhetoric (Plato, 1993, 278b 4–5: 201,
264e 5–7).
As with Aristotle, he recognizes that through imitation, as an in-
herent impulse, “a kind’ of learning is realized (μανθάνειν τί συμβαίνει/
manthanein ti symvainei), accompanied with a certain feeling of pleas-
ure which derives from the syllogism that the object of imitation is
identified with the prototype (Aristotle, Rhetoric, I, x–xi, 1371b: 176).
McKeon holds the opinion that Aristotle doesn’t invoke the imitation
of prior orators (1936: 27) despite Aristotle’s lessons about arguments
from example and about exemplar heros – both as models praiseworthy
to be imitated.
The history of the vigorous support of imitation as a method of ac-
quiring rhetorical excellence has begun. It is accepted that Isocrates
first highlighted its guaranteed role in the successful practice of philos-
ophy. In his Against the Sophists, he attributes to the teacher – conse-
quently to himself – the obligation to function as a model for his stu-
dents in order to help them “appear more florid and graceful” (Cagarin,
2000: 65). Also, in the theoretical framework of Isocrates’ paideia, imi-
tation should be practiced, equally, at three levels; at the level of action,
of thought and of speech (Haskins, 2000: 18, 22). It is due to imitative
exercises of various kinds of discourse that Isocrates inserted imitation
in the field of writing because of its close relation to exercitatio (practice)
(Fleming, 2003: 109; Kinneavy, 1984: 74).
2. Historic Roots of Imitatio in Rhetorical Pedagogy
2.1. The Ancient Theoretical Pedigree
Sophistic rhetoric identifies imitation as a necessary factor of the de-
velopment of successful orators. Besides, sophists are considered the first
imitators of oral rhapsodies (Schiappa, 1999: 6).
As regards Plato and Aristotle, they both accept the contribution of
imitation to learning even if they don’t perceive it as an emulating prac-
tice (Corbett, 1971: 243). For Plato, the positive or negative evaluation
of imitation depends on its role in the acquisition of the ideal truth. Fi-
nally, he approves its use as a medium capable of educating the Republic’s
future, ideal citizens (Plato, 1937; Tate, 1932: 161).
In Phaedrus Socrates presents an analogous bilateral attitude to-
wards it. On the one hand, he applies the art of imitation by offer-
ing a more accurate version of Lysias’ speech and he accepts, explicit-
ly, the existence of ideal models of orators. On the other hand, he ad-
vises Phaedrus not to imitate entirely a speech which contains bad ex-
amples of what he considers as true rhetoric (Plato, 1993, 278b 4–5: 201,
264e 5–7).
As with Aristotle, he recognizes that through imitation, as an in-
herent impulse, “a kind’ of learning is realized (μανθάνειν τί συμβαίνει/
manthanein ti symvainei), accompanied with a certain feeling of pleas-
ure which derives from the syllogism that the object of imitation is
identified with the prototype (Aristotle, Rhetoric, I, x–xi, 1371b: 176).
McKeon holds the opinion that Aristotle doesn’t invoke the imitation
of prior orators (1936: 27) despite Aristotle’s lessons about arguments
from example and about exemplar heros – both as models praiseworthy
to be imitated.
The history of the vigorous support of imitation as a method of ac-
quiring rhetorical excellence has begun. It is accepted that Isocrates
first highlighted its guaranteed role in the successful practice of philos-
ophy. In his Against the Sophists, he attributes to the teacher – conse-
quently to himself – the obligation to function as a model for his stu-
dents in order to help them “appear more florid and graceful” (Cagarin,
2000: 65). Also, in the theoretical framework of Isocrates’ paideia, imi-
tation should be practiced, equally, at three levels; at the level of action,
of thought and of speech (Haskins, 2000: 18, 22). It is due to imitative
exercises of various kinds of discourse that Isocrates inserted imitation
in the field of writing because of its close relation to exercitatio (practice)
(Fleming, 2003: 109; Kinneavy, 1984: 74).